tcs math – some mathematics of theoretical computer science

September 26, 2008

Lecture 2: Spectral partitioning and near-optimal foams

Filed under: CSE 599S, lecture, Math — Tags: , , , — James Lee @ 2:09 am

In the last lecture, we reduced the problem of cheating in \mathcal G_m^{\otimes k} (the k-times repeated m-cycle game) to finding a small set of edges \mathcal E in (\mathbb Z_m^k)_\infty whose removal eliminates all topologically non-trivial cycles.  Such a set \mathcal E is called a spine. To get some intuition about how many edges such a spine should contain, let’s instead look at a continuous variant of the problem.

Spines, Foams, and Isoperimetry

Consider again the k-dimensional torus \mathcal T^k = \mathbb R^k/\mathbb Z^k, which one can think of as \lbrack 0,1)^k with opposite sides identified.  Say that a nice set (e.g. a compact, C^\infty surface) \mathcal E \subseteq \mathcal T^k is a spine if it intersects every non-contractible loop in \mathcal T^k.  This is the continuous analog of a spine in (\mathbb Z_m^k)_\infty.  We will try to find such a spine \mathcal E with surface area, i.e. \mathrm{Vol}_{k-1}(\mathcal E), as small as possible.

Let’s consider some easy bounds.  First, it is clear that the set

\displaystyle \mathcal E = \left\{(x_1, \ldots, x_k) \in [0,1)^k : \exists i \in \{1,2,\ldots,k\}, x_i = 0\right\}

is a spine with \mathrm{Vol}_{k-1}(\mathcal E) = k.  (A moment’s thought shows that this is “equivalent” to the provers playing independent games in each coordinate of \mathcal G_m^{\otimes k}.)

To get a good lower bound, it helps to relate spines to foams which tile \mathbb R^k according to \mathbb Z^k, as follows.  Take two potential spines.

To determine which curve is actually a spine, we can repeatedly tile them side-by-side.

The first tiling contains the blue bi-infinite curve, which obviously gives a non-trivial cycle in \mathcal T^k, while the second yields a tiling of \mathbb R^k by bodies of volume 1.  It is easy to deduce the following claim.

Claim: A surface \mathcal E \subseteq \mathcal T^k is a spine if and only if it induces a tiling of the plane by bodies of volume 1 which is invariant under shifts by \mathbb Z^k.

By the isoperimetric inequality in \mathbb R^k, this immediately yields the bound

\displaystyle \mathrm{Vol}_{k-1}(\mathcal E) \geq \mathrm{Vol}_{k-1}(S^{k-1}) \approx \sqrt{k},

where S^{k-1} is the unit (k-1)-dimensional sphere.

So the the surface area of an optimal spine lies somewhere between k and \sqrt{k}.  On the one hand, cubes tile very nicely but have large surface area.  On the other hand, we have sphere-like objects which have small surface area, but don’t seem (at least intuitively) to tile very well at all.  As first evidence that this isn’t quite right, note that it is known how to cover \mathbb R^k by disjoint bodies of volume at most 1 so that the surface area/volume ratio grows like \sqrt{k}.  See Lemma 3.16 in this paper, which is based on Chekuri, et. al.  It’s just that these covers are not invariant under \mathbb Z^k shifts.

Before we reveal the answer, let’s see what consequences the corresponding discrete bounds would have for parallel repetition of the m-cycle game.  If the “cube bound” were tight, we would have \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G_m^{\otimes k}) \approx 1 - \frac{k}{m}, which doesn’t rule out a strong parallel repetition theorem (\alpha^*=1 in the previous lecture).  If the “sphere bound” were tight, we would have \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G_m^{\otimes k}) \approx 1 - \frac{\sqrt{k}}{m}, which shows that \alpha^* \geq 2.   In the latter case, the approach to proving equivalence of the UGC and MAX-CUT conjectures doesn’t even get off the ground.

As the astute reader might have guessed, recently Ran Raz proved that \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G_m^{\otimes k}) \geq 1 - C\frac{\sqrt{k}}{m} for some constant C > 0, showing that a strong parallel repetition theorem—even for unique games—is impossible.   Subsequently, Kindler, O’Donnell, Rao, and Wigderson showed that there exists a spine \mathcal E \subseteq \mathcal T^k with \mathrm{Vol}_{k-1}(\mathcal E) \approx \sqrt{k}.  While it is not difficult to show that the continuous result implies Raz’s discrete result, we will take a direct approach found recently by Alon and Klartag.

(more…)

September 21, 2008

Lecture 1: Cheating with foams

Filed under: CSE 599S, lecture, Math — Tags: , , — James Lee @ 1:35 pm

This the first lecture for CSE 599S:  Analytical and geometric methods in the theory of computation.  Today we’ll consider the gap amplification problem for 2-prover games, and see how it’s intimately related to some high-dimensional isoperimetric problems about foams.  In the next lecture, we’ll use spectral techniques to find approximately optimal foams (which will then let us cheat at repeated games).

The PCP Theorem, 2-prover games, and parallel repetition

For a 3-CNF formula \varphi, let \mathsf{sat}(\varphi) denote the maximum fraction of clauses in \varphi which are simultaneously satisfiable. For instance, \varphi is satisfiable if and only if \mathsf{sat}(\varphi)=1. One equivalent formulation of the PCP Theorem is that the following problem is NP-complete:

Formulation 1.

Given a 3-CNF formula \varphi, answer YES if \mathsf{sat}(\varphi)=1 and NO if \mathsf{sat}(\varphi) \leq 0.9 (any answer is acceptable if neither condition holds).

We can restate this result in the language of 2-prover games. A 2-prover game \mathcal G consists of four finite sets Q,Q',A,A', where Q and Q' are sets of questions, while A and A' are sets of answers to the questions in Q and Q', respectively. There is also a verifier V : Q \times Q' \times A \times A' \to \{0,1\} which checks the validity of answers. For a pair of questions (q,q') and answers (a,a'), the verifier is satisfied if and only if V(q,q',a,a')=1. The final component of \mathcal G is a probability distribution \mu on Q \times Q'.

Now a strategy for the game consists of two provers P : Q \to A and P' : Q' \to A' who map questions to answers. The score of the two provers (P,P') is precisely

\displaystyle\mathsf{val}_{P,P'}(\mathcal G) = \Pr \left[V(q, q', P(q), P(q'))=1\vphantom{\bigoplus}\right],

where (q,q') is drawn from \mu. This is just the probability that the verifier is happy with the answers provided by the two provers. The value of the game is now defined as

\displaystyle\mathsf{val}(\mathcal G) = \max_{P,P'} \mathsf{val}_{P,P'}(\mathcal G),

i.e. the best-possible score achievable by any two provers.

Now we can again restate the PCP Theorem as saying that the following problem is NP-complete:

Formulation 2.

Given a 2-prover game with \mathcal G with |A|,|A'|=O(1), answer YES if \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G)=1 and answer NO if \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G) \leq 0.99.

To see that Formulation 1 implies Formulation 2, consider, for any 3-CNF formula \varphi, the game \mathcal G_{\varphi} defined as follows. Q is the set of clauses in \varphi, Q' is the set of variables in \varphi, while A = \{ TTT, TTF, TFT, FTT, TFF, FTF, FFT, FFF \} and A' = \{T, F\}. Here A represents the set of eight possible truth assignments to a three-variable clause, and A' represents the set of possible truth assignments to a variable.

The distribution \mu is defined as follows: Choose first a uniformly random clause C \in Q, and then uniformly at random one of the three variables x \in Q' which appears in C. An answer (a_C, a_x) \in A \times A' is valid if the assignment a_C makes C true, and if a_x and a_C are consistent in the sense that they give the same truth value to the variable x. The following statement is an easy exercise:

For every 3-CNF formula \varphi, we have \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G_{\varphi}) = \frac23 + \frac13 \mathsf{sat}(\varphi).

The best strategy is to choose an assignment \mathcal A to the variables in \varphiP' plays according to \mathcal A, while P plays according to \mathcal A unless he is about to answer with an assignment that doesn’t satisfy the clause C.   At that point, he flips one of the literals to make his assignment satisfying (in this case, the chance of catching P cheating is only 1/3, the probability that P' is sent the variable that P flipped).

This completes our argument that Formulation 1 implies Formulation 2.

Parallel repetition
A very natural question is whether the constant 0.9 in Formulation 2 can be replaced by 0.001 (or an arbitrarily small constant). A natural way of gap amplification is by “parallel repetition” of a given game. Starting with a game \mathcal G = \langle Q,Q',A,A',V,\mu \rangle, we can consider the game \mathcal G^{\otimes k} = \langle Q^k, Q'^k, A^k, A'^k, V^{\otimes k}, \mu^{\otimes k} \rangle, where \mu^{\otimes k} is just the product distribution on (Q \times Q')^k \cong Q^k \times Q'^k. Here, we choose k pairs of questions (q_1, q'_1), \ldots, (q_k, q'_k) i.i.d. from \mu and the two provers then respond with answers (a_1, \ldots, a_k) \in A^k and (a'_1, \ldots, a'_k) \in A'^k. The verifier V^{\otimes k} is satisfied if and only if V(q_i, q'_i, a_i, a'_i)=1 for every i = 1, 2, \ldots, k.

Clearly \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G^{\otimes k}) \geq \mathsf{val}(G)^k because given a strategy (P,P') for \mathcal G, we can play the same strategy in every coordinate, and then our probability to win is just the probability that we simultaneously win k independent games. But is there a more clever strategy that can do better? Famously, early papers in this arena assumed it was obvious that \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G^{\otimes k}) = \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G)^k.

In fact, there are easy examples of games \mathcal G where \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G^{\otimes 2}) = \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G) = \frac12.  (Exercise: Show that this is true for the following game devised by Uri Feige. The verifier chooses two independent random bits b, b' \in \{0,1\}, and sends b to P and b' to P'. The answers of the two provers are from the set \{1,2\} \times \{0,1\}. The verifier accepts if both provers answer (1,b) or both provers answer (2,b').)

Nevertheless, in a seminal work, Ran Raz proved the Parallel Repetition Theorem, which states that the value of the repeated game does, in fact, drop exponentially.

Theorem 1.1: For every 2-prover game \mathcal G, there exists a constant c = O(\log(|A|+|A'|)) such that if \mathsf{val}(\mathcal G) \leq 1-\epsilon, then for every k \in \mathbb N,

\displaystyle\mathsf{val}(\mathcal G^{\otimes k}) \leq (1-\epsilon^{3})^{k/c}.

The exponent 3 above is actually due to an improvement of Holenstein (Raz’s original paper can be mined for an exponent of 32).

(more…)

The Shocking Blue Green Theme. Blog at WordPress.com.

Follow

Get every new post delivered to your Inbox.

Join 64 other followers